If Voltaire's Candide
is primarily a philosophical tract to discredit Gottfried Leibniz,
Voltaire certainly succeeds. However, if we seek practical answers to
the problem of evil, the sins of men, and extreme social inequality,
Candide comes up
short, raising more problems than solutions. Kasaipwalova, Grace,
and King, with echoes of Candide,
offer inspiring (if not perfect) solutions.
At the apex of the novel,
Candide and Cacambo are free to remain in the peaceful and equal city
of gold. However, Candide misses Cunegonde, and furthermore, Candide
realizes that borrowing the “pebbles,” the “yellow clay” of
El Dorado will make them “richer than all the kings in Europe”
(46). Candide desires to live in an unequal society, and the King of
El Dorado happily obliges their request for treasure-laden sheep. The
reader may sympathize with Candide's innocence in the first half of
the novel, but now Candide is undeniably wealthy and somewhat selfish
in his motives. Now when Candide, who can throw around enormous sums
of money to achieve his ends, is the victim of thieves such as the
Venice-bound skipper and the seductive Marchioness, it's difficult to
sympathize with our hero. But Candide isn't without heart. When he
hires Martin for companionship, and when the denied companions
complain of “injustice,” Candide throws money at them to keep
them quiet (51). At the novel's end, Candide and Cocambo realize
their desire to own their own kingdom—a human-created Eden.
Voltaire succeeds in convincing both Candide and the reader that the
world is far from perfect.
Perhaps Candide's response to
inequality and suffering can then be summarized as charitable
giving and isolation.
Neither of these responses are satisfying under the standard of true
justice. The mother in Thomas King's “Borders” refuses to deny
her ethnic heritage, changing hearts and laws in the process. John
Kasaipwalova gives us a David-and-Goliath story for the post-colonial
era. I am struck, and torn, by the response of Patricia Grace's
characters to losing their native lands. This story, like many of the
destitute characters in Candide,
reminds me of the classic moral scenario in which a hungry man is
justified in stealing a loaf of bread. Many of the characters Candide
encounters live in similar situations, and the philosophy of Leibniz
(as well as the pennies thrown to them by Candide) don't resolve the
injustice, but only dull the pain. While I don't know if I agree with
the route taken by Grace's characters, they provide an example of
positive action, rather than hiding from suffering. Voltaire suggests
that suffering is caused by the sins of men (and there are plenty of
those in Candide,
especially in Paquette's sexual repression). But Candide, as well as
these short tales, also raise questions of structural
justice—including civil disobedience or finding loopholes in a law.
Is suffering a result of structures or individuals, or both? The
answer to that question—and the practical solutions to
injustice—might not be found in the Garden of Eden.